Loading [MathJax]/jax/output/CommonHTML/jax.js

Cardinal Numbers

The present unit is part of the following walks

Introduction

Please note that the text on this web page only gives a short summary of the Unit Cardinal Numbers. The full text including explanations, proofs and historical notes is available as a separate pdf-document at the end of this page.


The present unit is the 4th unit of the walk The Cardinality of Sets.


You will learn the meaning of the following terms:


The main results of this unit are:



The Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein

Definition. Two sets A and B are called equivalent if there exists a bijective function α:AB from the set A onto the set B. If A and B are two equivalent sets, we write AB.


Definition. Let A and B be two sets.

(a) We say that the set B dominates the set A if there exists a subset B of the set B equivalent to the set A, that is, there exists a bijective function α:AB from the set A onto a subset B of the set B.

(b) If the set B dominates the set A, then we write AB.

(c) If the set B dominates the set A and if the sets A and B are not equivalent, then we say that the set B strictly dominates the set A. In this case, we write AB.


Theorem. Let A and B be two non-empty sets. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

(i) The set B dominates the set A, that is, AB.

(ii) There exists an injective function α:AB from the set A into the set B.

(iii) There exists a surjective function β:BA from the set B onto the set A.


Theorem. (Cantor and Bernstein) Let A and B be two sets.

If AB and BA, then we have AB.


Corollary. Let A, B and C be three sets.

(a) We have AA (reflexivity).

(b) We have AB and BA if and only if AB (symmetry).

(c) If AB and BC, then we have AC (transitivity).


Theorem. Let A and B be two sets, and suppose that there exist two injective functions α:AB and β:BA. Then there exists a bijective function γ:AB.



Further Proofs of the Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein

The proof of Dedekind and Zermelo is based on the following theorem:


Theorem. (Dedekind and Zermelo) Let A be a set which is equivalent to a subset B of the set A. If C is subset of the set A with

BCA,

then the set C is equivalent to the sets A and B.



The Comparability Theorem

Theorem. (Comparability Theorem) Let A and B be two sets. Then we have AB or BA.


Theorem. Let A and B be two sets. Then exactly one of the following cases occurs:

(i) We have AB.

(ii) We have AB.

(iii) We have BA.



A Second Proof of the Comparability Theorem

The second proof of the comparability theorem is based on the Lemma of Zorn:


Theorem. (Lemma of Zorn) Let A=(A,) be a partially ordered set such that every chain C of the set A has an upper bound in the set A. (A chain of the set A is a totally ordered subset of the set A.)

Then the set A contains a maximal element.



Cardinal Numbers

Definition. Let A=(A,) be an ordered set. The set A is called an ordinal number if the pair A=(A,) is well-ordered and if we have

a=Aa={xAx<a} for all aA.

In other words each element a of the set A equals the initial segment with respect to the element a.


Definition. Let A be an ordinal number. The ordinal number A is called a cardinal number if it fulfills the following condition: For each ordinal number B satisfying

BA and BA

we have B=A.


Theorem. Let A be a set. Then there exists exactly one cardinal number a such that Aa.


Definition. Let A be a set, and let a be the unique cardinal number with Aa (Theorem [#card-th-cardinality]). The cardinal number a is called the cardinality of the set A. It is denoted by |A|:=a.


French / German. Cardinality of a set = Cardinalité = Kardinalität or Mächtigkeit.


Theorem. Let A and B be two sets. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

(i) The sets A and B are equivalent.

(ii) We have |A|=|B|.


Theorem. Let A be a non-empty set. There does not exist a set A such that

XA if and only if XA.

In other words, the sets equivalent to the set A do not form a set.



The Order of the Cardinal Numbers

Definition. Let a and b be two cardinal numbers. We set

(a) ab if and only if ab.

(b) a<b if and only if ab.

(c) ab if and only if ba.

(d) a>b if and only if ba.

The so-defined relation on each set of cardinal numbers is called the standard order on the cardinal numbers.


French / German. Standard order on the cardinal numbers = Ordre standard sur le nombres ordineaux = Standardordnung auf den Kardinalzahlen.


Theorem. Let A, B and C be three sets, and let be the standard order of the cardinal numbers.

(a) We have |A||A|.

(b) If |A||B| and |B||A|, then we have |A|=|B|.

(c) If |A||B| and |B||C|, then we have |A||C|.

(d) Let A and B be two sets. Then we either have |A|=|B| or |A|<|B| or |A|>|B|.


Theorem. Let A and B be two sets.

(a) The following conditions are equivalent:

(i) We have AB.

(ii) We have |A||B|.

(iii) We have |A||B|.

(b) The following conditions are equivalent:

(i) We have AB.

(ii) We have |A|<|B|.

(iii) We have |A||B|.

(iv) We have |A||B|.


Corollary. Let A and B be two sets. The following conditions are equivalent:

(i) We have |A||B|.

(ii) There exists an injective mapping α:AB from the set A into the set B.

(iii) There exists a surjective mapping β:BA from the set B onto the set A.


Corollary. (a) Let A and B be two sets. If the set A is a subset of the set B, then we have |A||B|.

(b) Let a and b be two cardinal numbers with ab. Then there exist two sets A and B such that

|A|=a,|B|=b and AB.



The Theorem of Cantor

Theorem. (Cantor) Let A be an arbitrary set. Then we have

|A|<|P(A)|

where P(A) denotes the power set of the set A.


Theorem. Let A be a set. Then the following set exists:

A:={X ordinal number XA}.


Theorem. Let A be a set. Then we have

|A|=min{X ordinal number XA}.


Theorem. (a) There does not exist a set C with the following property:

XC if and only if X is a cardinal number

in other words, the cardinal numbers do not form a set.

(b) There does not exist a set C with the following property:

XC if and only if X is a ordinal number

in other words, the ordinal numbers do not form a set.



Finite Sets

Definition. (a) A set A is called {\bf finite} if it is equivalent to a natural number n, that is, if there exists a natural number n such that An.

In this case we say that {\bf the set A has n elements}, and we write |A|=n.

(b) If a set A is not finite, then it is called {\bf infinite}. In this case we write |A|=.


Theorem. Every natural number is a cardinal number.


Theorem. The set N0 of the natural numbers is a cardinal number.


Definition. The cardinal number N0 is denoted by 0 (speak: Alef zero). ( is the first letter of the hebrew alphabet.)



Infinite Sets

Theorem. For each set A, the following conditions are equivalent:

(i) The set A is infinite.

(ii) We have N0A.

(iii) We have N0=|N0||A|.


Theorem. Let A be a set. Then the following two conditions are equivalent:

(i) The set A is infinite.

(ii) There exists a proper subset B of the set A and a bijective function α:AB from the set A onto the set B.


Definition. A set A is called countable if we have AN0, and it is called countably infinite if we have AN0.


Proposition. (a) Every subset of the set N0 is countable.

(b) Every subset of a countable set is countable.



Notes and References

A list of textbooks about set theory is contained in Unit [Literature about Set Theory].


Do you want to learn more? In Unit [Cardinal Arithmetic – in preparation] we will extend the elementary operations m+n, mn and mn from the natural numbers to general cardinal numbers. We will explain equations and inequalities like

a+a=a,aa=a and 2a>a for all infinite cardinal numbers a.



Download

Cardinal Numbers

The pdf document is the full text including the proofs.

Current Version: 1.0.0 from January 2021