
Cardinal Numbers
- Introduction
- The Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein
- Further Proofs of the Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein
- The Comparability Theorem
- A Second Proof of the Comparability Theorem
- Cardinal Numbers
- The Order of the Cardinal Numbers
- The Theorem of Cantor
- Finite Sets
- Infinite Sets
- Notes and References
- Download
Introduction
Please note that the text on this web page only gives a short summary of the Unit Cardinal Numbers. The full text including explanations, proofs and historical notes is available as a separate pdf-document at the end of this page.
The present unit is the 4th unit of the walk The Cardinality of Sets.
You will learn the meaning of the following terms:
- A set B (strictly) dominates a set A
- Cardinal Number
- Cardinality of a Set
- Standard Order on the Cardinal Numbers
- The Cardinal Number ℵ0
- Countable Set
The main results of this unit are:
- The Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein (see Theorem [#card-th-cantor-bernstein])
- The Theorem of Dedekind and Zermelo (see Theorem [#card-th-cardinality-between])
- The Comparability Theorem (see Theorem [#card-th-comparability-theorem])
- Existence of a unique cardinal number a such that |A|=a (see Theorem [#card-th-cardinality])
- The sets equivalent to a set A≠∅ do not form a set (see Theorem [#card-th-sim-n-no-set])
- The Theorem of Cantor (see Theorem [#card-th-cantor-x-smaller-p-x])
- We have |A|=min:{X ordinal number ∣X∼A} (see Theorem [#card-th-definition-cardinality])
- The cardinal numbers do not form a set (see Theorem [#card-th-cardinal-numbers-no-set])
- The ordinal numbers do not form a set (see Theorem [#card-th-cardinal-numbers-no-set])
- Every natural number is a cardinal number (see Theorem [#card-th-natural-number-cardinal-number])
- The set N0 of the natural numbers is a cardinal number (see Theorem [#card-th-nz0-cardinal-number])
- A set A is infinite if and only if N0≤|A| (see Theorem [#card-th-nz0-smaller-a-infinite])
- A set A is infinite if and only if there exists a bijective mapping α:A→B from the set A onto a proper subset B of the set A (see Theorem [#card-th-infinite-subset-bijective])
The Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein
Definition. Two sets A and B are called equivalent if there exists a bijective function α:A→B from the set A onto the set B. If A and B are two equivalent sets, we write A∼B.
Definition. Let A and B be two sets.
(a) We say that the set B dominates the set A if there exists a subset B′ of the set B equivalent to the set A, that is, there exists a bijective function α:A→B′ from the set A onto a subset B′ of the set B.
(b) If the set B dominates the set A, then we write A⪯B.
(c) If the set B dominates the set A and if the sets A and B are not equivalent, then we say that the set B strictly dominates the set A. In this case, we write A≺B.
Theorem. Let A and B be two non-empty sets. Then the following conditions are equivalent:
(i) The set B dominates the set A, that is, A⪯B.
(ii) There exists an injective function α:A→B from the set A into the set B.
(iii) There exists a surjective function β:B→A from the set B onto the set A.
Theorem. (Cantor and Bernstein) Let A and B be two sets.
If A⪯B and B⪯A, then we have A∼B.
Corollary. Let A, B and C be three sets.
(a) We have A⪯A (reflexivity).
(b) We have A⪯B and B⪯A if and only if A∼B (symmetry).
(c) If A⪯B and B⪯C, then we have A⪯C (transitivity).
Theorem. Let A and B be two sets, and suppose that there exist two injective functions α:A→B and β:B→A. Then there exists a bijective function γ:A→B.
Further Proofs of the Theorem of Cantor and Bernstein
The proof of Dedekind and Zermelo is based on the following theorem:
Theorem. (Dedekind and Zermelo) Let A be a set which is equivalent to a subset B of the set A. If C is subset of the set A with
B⊆C⊆A,
then the set C is equivalent to the sets A and B.
The Comparability Theorem
Theorem. (Comparability Theorem) Let A and B be two sets. Then we have A⪯B or B⪯A.
Theorem. Let A and B be two sets. Then exactly one of the following cases occurs:
(i) We have A∼B.
(ii) We have A≺B.
(iii) We have B≺A.
A Second Proof of the Comparability Theorem
The second proof of the comparability theorem is based on the Lemma of Zorn:
Theorem. (Lemma of Zorn) Let A=(A,≤) be a partially ordered set such that every chain C of the set A has an upper bound in the set A. (A chain of the set A is a totally ordered subset of the set A.)
Then the set A contains a maximal element.
Cardinal Numbers
Definition. Let A=(A,≤) be an ordered set. The set A is called an ordinal number if the pair A=(A,≤) is well-ordered and if we have
a=Aa={x∈A∣x<a} for all a∈A.
In other words each element a of the set A equals the initial segment with respect to the element a.
Definition. Let A be an ordinal number. The ordinal number A is called a cardinal number if it fulfills the following condition: For each ordinal number B satisfying
B⊆A and B∼A
we have B=A.
Theorem. Let A be a set. Then there exists exactly one cardinal number a such that A∼a.
Definition. Let A be a set, and let a be the unique cardinal number with A∼a (Theorem [#card-th-cardinality]). The cardinal number a is called the cardinality of the set A. It is denoted by |A|:=a.
French / German. Cardinality of a set = Cardinalité = Kardinalität or Mächtigkeit.
Theorem. Let A and B be two sets. Then the following conditions are equivalent:
(i) The sets A and B are equivalent.
(ii) We have |A|=|B|.
Theorem. Let A be a non-empty set. There does not exist a set A such that
X∈A if and only if X∼A.
In other words, the sets equivalent to the set A do not form a set.
The Order of the Cardinal Numbers
Definition. Let a and b be two cardinal numbers. We set
(a) a≤b if and only if a⊆b.
(b) a<b if and only if a⊂b.
(c) a≥b if and only if b⊆a.
(d) a>b if and only if b⊂a.
The so-defined relation ≤ on each set of cardinal numbers is called the standard order on the cardinal numbers.
French / German. Standard order on the cardinal numbers = Ordre standard sur le nombres ordineaux = Standardordnung auf den Kardinalzahlen.
Theorem. Let A, B and C be three sets, and let ≤ be the standard order of the cardinal numbers.
(a) We have |A|≤|A|.
(b) If |A|≤|B| and |B|≤|A|, then we have |A|=|B|.
(c) If |A|≤|B| and |B|≤|C|, then we have |A|≤|C|.
(d) Let A and B be two sets. Then we either have |A|=|B| or |A|<|B| or |A|>|B|.
Theorem. Let A and B be two sets.
(a) The following conditions are equivalent:
(i) We have A⪯B.
(ii) We have |A|≤|B|.
(iii) We have |A|⊆|B|.
(b) The following conditions are equivalent:
(i) We have A≺B.
(ii) We have |A|<|B|.
(iii) We have |A|⊂|B|.
(iv) We have |A|∈|B|.
Corollary. Let A and B be two sets. The following conditions are equivalent:
(i) We have |A|≤|B|.
(ii) There exists an injective mapping α:A→B from the set A into the set B.
(iii) There exists a surjective mapping β:B→A from the set B onto the set A.
Corollary. (a) Let A and B be two sets. If the set A is a subset of the set B, then we have |A|≤|B|.
(b) Let a and b be two cardinal numbers with a≤b. Then there exist two sets A and B such that
|A|=a,|B|=b and A⊆B.
The Theorem of Cantor
Theorem. (Cantor) Let A be an arbitrary set. Then we have
|A|<|P(A)|
where P(A) denotes the power set of the set A.
Theorem. Let A be a set. Then the following set exists:
A:={X ordinal number ∣X∼A}.
Theorem. Let A be a set. Then we have
|A|=min{X ordinal number ∣X∼A}.
Theorem. (a) There does not exist a set C with the following property:
X∈C if and only if X is a cardinal number
in other words, the cardinal numbers do not form a set.
(b) There does not exist a set C with the following property:
X∈C if and only if X is a ordinal number
in other words, the ordinal numbers do not form a set.
Finite Sets
Definition. (a) A set A is called {\bf finite} if it is equivalent to a natural number n, that is, if there exists a natural number n such that A∼n.
In this case we say that {\bf the set A has n elements}, and we write |A|=n.
(b) If a set A is not finite, then it is called {\bf infinite}. In this case we write |A|=∞.
Theorem. Every natural number is a cardinal number.
Theorem. The set N0 of the natural numbers is a cardinal number.
Definition. The cardinal number N0 is denoted by ℵ0 (speak: Alef zero). (ℵ is the first letter of the hebrew alphabet.)
Infinite Sets
Theorem. For each set A, the following conditions are equivalent:
(i) The set A is infinite.
(ii) We have N0⪯A.
(iii) We have N0=|N0|≤|A|.
Theorem. Let A be a set. Then the following two conditions are equivalent:
(i) The set A is infinite.
(ii) There exists a proper subset B of the set A and a bijective function α:A→B from the set A onto the set B.
Definition. A set A is called countable if we have A⪯N0, and it is called countably infinite if we have A∼N0.
Proposition. (a) Every subset of the set N0 is countable.
(b) Every subset of a countable set is countable.
Notes and References
A list of textbooks about set theory is contained in Unit [Literature about Set Theory].
Do you want to learn more? In Unit [Cardinal Arithmetic – in preparation] we will extend the elementary operations m+n, m⋅n and mn from the natural numbers to general cardinal numbers. We will explain equations and inequalities like
a+a=a,a⋅a=a and 2a>a for all infinite cardinal numbers a.
Download
Cardinal Numbers
The pdf document is the full text including the proofs.
Current Version: 1.0.0 from January 2021